To What Extent is Reconciliation an Appropriate Term in Post-Conflict Societies?

This content was originally written for an undergraduate or Master's program. It is published as part of our mission to showcase peer-leading papers written by students during their studies. This work can be used for background reading and research, but should not be cited as an expert source or used in place of scholarly articles/books.

‘Reconciliation’ is a hotly-contested component of post-conflict analysis. There is ample discussion amongst scholars and practitioners concerning the value of the term—a debate characterized by pragmatism, idealism, and an inevitable undercurrent of emotion. The concept, as a constituent of transitional justice, gained international prominence following the Second World War, and more recently through the use of Truth and Reconciliation Commissions (TRC). Many theorists and practitioners have since come to consider reconciliation as the natural objective of a conflict-cycle— the final phase where the previously warring parties embrace some degree of peace. This position, however, is becoming less clear-cut.

This essay will explore to what extent the term ‘reconciliation’ is both appropriate following the atrocities in post-conflict societies, and further, what level of reconciliation is realistic to expect in new post-conflict societies. It will do this by first defining what is meant by reconciliation. Secondly, the essay will examine the limitations of ‘thick’ reconciliation. Third, it will challenge long-held assumptions about reconciliation by drawing on cases that suggest a different ‘thin’ level of reconciliation that can be witnessed after conflict. Fourthly, building on these respective critiques and endorsements, it seek to find a theoretical middle-ground that reflects at least some of the idealistic intent of ‘thick’ reconciliation on a micro-level. Through this, the essay will argue that although ‘thick’ reconciliation is unlikely, the pragmatism of ‘thin’ reconciliation allows for compromises that result in some degree of peace and co-existence. This ‘thin’ interpretation can then be built upon to create a stronger mandate for the term that prevents reoccurrences of future violence.

Definition

Although the definition of ‘reconciliation’ is problematic, the conceptual framework of this essay is relatively straightforward. Ironically, scholars can only agree that reconciliation cannot be simply defined. Pankhurst notes that theoretical definitions tend to encompass an ‘amalgam’ of literal interpretations of the term, often leaving reconciliation research neglectful of either individuals or larger groups.[1] Focusing research on different levels engenders different political and emotional contexts that can be hazardous to reconciliation projects. However, despite this confusion, it can be deconstructed to clarify the concept.

This essay contends that there are two types of reconciliation: regenerative and functional.[2] One is appropriate, the other is not. Regenerative, or ‘thick’, reconciliation assumes a ‘restoration of peaceful relationships’ that resonates at an individual level.[3] This demand for an institutionalization of deep healing can be considered unrealistic due to the high expectations that it places on societies recovering from a traumatic experience. In addition, the optimistic standards required for ‘thick’ reconciliation require more proactive legal mechanisms. This represents a positive-peace approach, whereby action is taken to promote peace—perhaps in the form of TRCs, intervention, or constitutional reform.

On the other hand, functional, or ‘thin’, reconciliation merely assumes ‘co-existence’, and the reframing of relationships within divided societies.[4] The requisite element here is a state of non-violence, whereby, for example, groups live together despite a lack of trust. This form of reconciliation is more realistic, as the minimalist interpretation of the key elements of reconciliation lowers expectations of post-conflict societies. Here, negative-peace approaches, such as disarmament and demobilization that simply stop violence, are more appropriate initial measures. Stripped of its idealism, functional reconciliation is more apparent in the cases that this essay will study; it is certainly more constructive when tackling reconciliation normatively.

That being said, reconciliation must be approached very carefully. It is a ‘grossly over-packed term’ that incorporates numerous abstract concepts.[5] Context is incredibly important as often one reconciliation attempt, even if it experienced some degree of success, may not be applicable in another scenario. Next, the limitations of the maximalist approach must be revealed.

Why It Is Inappropriate: ‘Thick’ Reconciliation

This section will argue that a more regenerative form of reconciliation, as envisaged by idealists, is unrealistic. The dichotomous relationship between thick and thin reconciliation can be characterized as either harmony or toleration.[6] Unlike thinner forms of the concept, ‘thick’ reconciliation places significant emphasis on ‘friendliness and forgiveness’.[7] Consequently, it is more difficult to achieve through macro level, top-down approaches to post-conflict.

Many scholars adopt a definition of reconciliation that implies the restoration of harmonious relationships and ‘changed psychological orientation towards the other’.[8] This represents the positive peace perspective: striving for genuine cooperative and peaceful relations instead of simply non-violence.[9] The principal challenge facing regenerative reconciliation is the ability to meet the lofty demands set by its main components. According to Lederach, there are four components of reconciliation: truth, justice, peace, and mercy.[10] To cite Souto: ‘in [Lederach’s] view, all these values must be satisfied in order to pave the way towards true reconciliation’.[11] To comprehensively satisfy them, positive-peace instruments are essential, as functional reconciliation can avoid some of these concepts entirely and still lead to ‘peaceful’ societies. Without a doubt, psychological healing and acceptance of others makes victims less likely to engage in future violence.[12] So in an ideal world, regenerative reconciliation should be the sole interpretation of the term. However, the realities of economic depression and a culture of violence in conflict zones suggest that the conditions required for complete reconciliation are unobtainable. In reality, satisfying just one, never mind finding a moral balance between the four concepts, is hugely problematic.

Regenerative reconciliation is critically hamstrung by the central theoretical assumption that ‘social harmony’ is the ideal outcome of the post-conflict process.[13] Bar-tal and Benninck are amongst several scholars who interpret it as the ‘outcome’.[14] Reconciliation as the ‘goal’ suggests the post-conflict process is designed to achieve a ‘restoration of genuinely peaceful relationships.’[15] Despite its value in providing citizens with a common goal through a grandiose narrative called the ‘rainbow nation’, this can be hazardous. Firstly, by publicly promoting a goal of reconciliation, it invites spoilers. Simply, some people will not want reconciliation.[16] It isolates certain victims in their own country, and will leave others nervous that the promise of national reconciliation may force them to ‘compromise and forgive perpetrators’.[17] At a micro-level, it might demand that a raped woman essentially forgive her rapist. At a macro-level, it might galvanize splinter groups that disagree with the reconciliatory message. In claiming that reconciliation ‘requires the support of the whole society’, Bar-Tal and Benninck defend this concept against potential spoilers by asserting that society can institutionalize reconciliation despite ‘marginal’ groups.[18] However, history has illustrated the power of marginal actors in post-conflict scenarios. Following the 2006 Darfur Peace Agreement, dissenting Arab militias who felt excluded from the process successfully destabilized the resulting ‘peace’, leading to increased violence.[19] Conceptually then, a framework that dismisses the threat from spoilers is short-sighted and ill-equipped to design structures that lead to positive peace.

Secondly, reconciliation as a ‘goal’ facilitates external influence, often to the detriment of the internal victims. A clear goal compliments the narrative and helps to measure success—a particularly important factor if states or organizations commit troops.[20] External actors are, therefore, more likely to act in situations where there is this clear objective, rather than in situations that envisage a long, cultural process that has no end in sight. Importantly, regenerative reconciliation demands that the victim be placed at the centre of moral concern, but goal-oriented narratives obfuscate this by employing rushed, top-down, macro-level solutions. Normatively then, targeting regenerative reconciliation means having a desired outcome. This can be troublesome, especially with a normative framework that offers the international community a significant role. For example, the international response to Rwanda, despite its good intentions, was clumsy and threatening to regenerative reconciliation. The International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR) left some ‘Rwandans unaffected and unreconciled by [the politicized nature of] its measures’.[21] Unsatisfactory efforts such as this not only make the victims resentful of external actors, but it risks leaving them disillusioned with reconciliation, making them less likely to fully engage with the long process.[22] The dangers associated with this approach suggest this kind of reconciliation is at best inappropriate, but at worst it can inculcate new fear that generates further violence.

The maximalist conditions imposed by positive-peace approaches lead to unrealistic expectations of reconciliation. Each of Lederach’s integral components are subjective concepts, sensitive to political context and personal interpretation. For example, a Western interpretation of justice created an inefficient, ad hoc ICTR, whereas a cultural understanding led to the Gacaca courts’ unique blend of punitive and restorative measures.[23] This contributes to what Hinton calls ‘global/local friction’, and what De Vos characterizes further as ‘competing narratives and disconnects between global conceptions of justice and lived realities’.[24] These ‘disconnects’ within Lederach’s holistic approach lead to the alienation of certain, unfulfilled victims. There is the tendency for external actors to arrive at a conflict zone armed only with a moral imperative and to deploy their ‘liberal normative goods’.[25] This is harmful as regenerative reconciliation cannot be forced or pushed through, particularly by an actor other than the post-conflict state. Ideally, the conceptual demands could only be satisfied with a tailor-made process for each victim, perpetrator and bystander—leaving total regenerative reconciliation an unlikely eventuality.

This section has outlined the limitations of regenerative reconciliation. Wide conceptual interpretation signifies certain top-down structures are destined to alienate some victims. It has examined these weaknesses primarily from a theoretical perspective, as there is not sufficient empirical support to suggest it is anything other than an idealistic vision. Even South Africa, noted for its ‘successful’ reconciliation, does not exhibit effective positive-peace approaches: relying on amnesties instead of judicial power.[26] Reconciliation as regenerative, therefore, is not an appropriate term. However, stripped of its unrealistic humanistic expectations, reconciliation regains its relevance, and can be properly applied to future situations. This will be examined in the following section.

Why It Is Appropriate: ‘Thin’ Reconciliation

In the case of ‘thin’ reconciliation, post-conflict scenarios that exhibit minimal levels of trust, peace, or justice demonstrate how a more minimalist interpretation of reconciliation is realistic and, therefore, appropriate.

Firstly, this essay must defend the legitimacy of functional reconciliation, as there are those who contest whether this minimalist approach to peace-building merits the label of reconciliation.[27] Simply, it is justified by its relative effectiveness. When adapting reconciliation to a ‘thin’ interpretation of non-violence, there are ample examples of societies that are reconciling. Clark draws on her fieldwork in the Balkans to highlight societies that ‘understood reconciliation in very minimalist terms’.[28] Certainly, there remains tension and suspicion, but nonetheless, there is co-existence. Although it is not regenerative reconciliation as understood by Lederach, it is an important first step: a step that can be normatively discussed as it is stripped of much of the emotion and psychology that is central to a deeper state of healing. Functional reconciliation is, therefore, appropriate due to its reduced standards of basic security and non-violence, and its pragmatism, which Bloomfield contends, ‘avoids ideals’.[29]

Clark’s work on functional trust is just one example of a minimalist approach to understanding reconciliation.[30] The relationship between Rwandan Gacaca courts and justice is insightful. These courts provided an alternative to Western justice.[31] It was a cultural legal mechanism that aimed to punish perpetrators, before reintegrating them into society. This represents functional justice as it is practical, it utilizes restorative justice, and it left many Tutsis in a position to ‘move on’. Many scholars are critical of this process. Complaints over substandard judges, the quality of truth generated by the courts, and the suggestion that the entire exercise is designed to reinforce Hutu guilt are prevalent.[32] It is an imperfect process whose flaws diminish its legitimacy. However, perhaps these critics are missing the point. Exacting justice in post-conflict scenarios is near-impossible. Prosecuting every génocidaire is illogical, while handing out amnesties is arguably immoral. What Gacaca does is give Tutsis their ‘day in court.’ The inconsistencies of the court mean a deep, regenerative healing might be unlikely, but it allowed Tutsis a position of judge and jury, in which their psyche can heal, and adjust to their new situation. This symbolic position of power counters the dehumanization they experienced as genocide victims. Consequently, the Rwandan ethnic conflict becomes less asymmetrical, allowing for greater engagement between the groups during the subsequent reconciliation efforts. Once again, this minimal level of transitional justice, as seen also in post-apartheid South Africa, is central to establishing non-violence, and starting the reconciliation process.

Bloomfield’s work suggests a shift in rationale when approaching reconciliation. As a practitioner, he strongly advocates a process-oriented understanding of reconciliation, the first step of which should be ‘co-existence’.[33] As a term it demands less of victims, it is not weighed down by maximalist understandings of subjective concepts, and it represents a much more achievable ‘end-state’ in post-conflict reconstruction.[34] It is also more acquiescent of negative-peace approaches, leaving states less vulnerable to clumsy Western attempts to force peace. Understanding reconciliation as a process is critical to its success. Reducing social, historical, and ethnic cleavages is a ‘long process’ that might take years for victims, perpetrators, and civilians to psychologically adapt and engage with their new situation.[35] Following the Northern Irish ceasefire in 1994 for example, the peace process continues to this day.[36] The negatively peaceful ceasefire led eventually to disarmament, the political normalization of Sinn Fein and relations that Prime Minister Cameron recently claimed to be at an ‘all time high’.[37] Negative measures are therefore constructive to the overall process, especially as a first step. Action such as disarmament and demobilization relegate external actors to a supervisory role, which has been effective in Nicaragua, Angola, and Egypt amongst others.[38] This essay promotes an organic, internal process for reconciliation. Simply, nobody knows how to reconnect a nation better than those that experienced the violence themselves.

Targeting reconciliation through a process has other advantages. It can consign the cathartic moment of reconciliation, as envisaged by idealists, to a secondary objective. Instead, states can focus their efforts on other projects that slowly build trust and peace. The best example of this is Franco-German relations following the Second World War. Applying Maoz’ joint-projects model, one can observe how mistrust and anger was slowly eroded during the cooperative construction of the European Union.[39] Here, economic integration was the objective, while reconciliation was simply a welcome by-product.[40] Hence, a ‘thin’ level of reconciliation is attainable without even explicitly targeting it. Economic and political stability are crucial to reconciliation, and are easily ignored when scholars submerge themselves in issues of trust, peace, and forgiveness, suggesting once again that an idealistic vision of reconciliation can be destructive.

This section has illustrated how, when stripped of its idealism, reconciliation is more realistic in post-conflict scenarios. Moreover, these reduced expectations can be achieved through uncontroversial negative-peace measures, which in turn limit the influence of external actors. It is important to conceive ‘thin’ reconciliation, or ‘co-existence’, as the first step of a lengthy process. Only then can victims truly re-experience what has happened, before actively engaging in reconciling their communities. This model, however, is still imperfect; the next section will build upon it to posit a more appropriate understanding of reconciliation.

Finding the Middle Ground?

Although empirical analysis suggests a more minimalist approach to reconciliation yields at least functional societies, there is, nonetheless, a lack of focus on reconciliation at a micro level, leaving victims unfulfilled at a personal level, which may prevent long-term peace. From an initial stage of ‘co-existence’, an ultimately regenerative reconciliation would be ideal; however, there is insufficient empirical support to suggest this can be normatively targeted. Although it is unlikely, the conceptual framework can be adapted to perhaps improve the odds of a more psychological reconciliation occurring.

The previous section outlined the capacity of ‘thin’ reconciliation to put societies in a position to move on. These measures, despite some degree of success, muffle the impact on a micro-level as they lack an element of contact. To cite Staub: ‘real contact is important for the beginnings of positive connection’.[41] Although this essay advocates a minimalist approach that demands compromise, it does not change the fact that the outcome of a reconciliation process should be citizens with a right to life, safety and happiness. This demands a normative framework that underlines the importance of bottom-up mechanisms that resonate on multiple levels. A complimentary approach between top-down and bottom-up approaches is valuable. Top-down focus should concentrate on the general stability of the state, whilst bottom-up ‘activism’ should slowly and informally tackle Lederach’s components of reconciliation. By targeting regenerative benefits this way, states can avoid objectifying the goal of reconciliation and they can restrict the influence of external actors. A helpful comparison might be between Northern Ireland and the North Caucasus. Northern Ireland has (somewhat) reconciled using a mixture of the two. Pursuant to The Good Friday Agreement, a negatively-peaceful ceasefire is ensured from a national level.[42] Meanwhile, grass roots campaigns such as Ardoyne Commemoration Project engage with more emotional post-conflict issues at a local level.[43] Subsequently, controversial themes such as truth-telling can organically progress without being under the auspices of a politically motivated government. On the other hand, despite significant input from the international community, a lack of resources and will severely constricts the bottom-up activity in Chechnya.[44] No methods by which the warring factions can communicate and ultimately empathize perpetuate the distance between the groups. Hence, sporadic outbursts of violence since the First Chechen War in 1994 are unsurprising. Contact is a crucial independent variable in reconciliation theory, and a framework that values it is much more likely to lead to near-regenerative reconciliation.

In addition to contact, there is another element that must be incorporated into reconciliation theory: a stable state. There is a lack of literature concerning the significance of stability during reconciliation. History suggests that the stronger the state, the more likely the reconciliation. Northern Ireland and South Africa have reached some level of peace, and both exhibit stable democracies and possess relative wealth. Hope, too, is crucial: contentedness is important to reconciliation, and is likely to grow if civilians feel secure in terms of human, political, and economic security. A comparison between Zimbabwe and Angola is insightful. Both experienced civil wars, resulting in a ‘peace process’.[45] Following a ceasefire, both employed the (dangerous) ‘forgive and forget’ strategy, encouraging citizens to start anew, and offering amnesties to perpetrators.[46] Today, Zimbabwe is in dictatorial turmoil, whereas Angola is thriving. Both attempted the ill thought-out strategy, so why the enormous chasm? Oil, perhaps. Since the conflict, Angola’s GDP has sky-rocketed thanks to oil deposits in and around the country.[47] Since their conflict, Mugabe’s isolated regime, in addition to destructive farming policy and widespread corruption, has left Zimbabwe 194th out of 195 countries in terms of GDP per capita.[48][49] Angola’s sensible economic management and domestic policies elevated the state to a position where it was better prepared to begin an emotional process. This is doubly pertinent as it relates to both domestic action, and also input from the international community. So despite its unusually ineffective approach, Angola succeeded in quelling civil violence, putting them on the path towards a more complete reconciliation. Economic prosperity creates a positive effect for a state, and this ‘feel-good’ factor is more likely to result in friendly inter-group relations.[50] To normatively address reconciliation, therefore, perhaps there needs to be more attention focused first on the state, rather than its reconciliation process. From there, ‘democratic reciprocity’ beckons.[51] This end-state of re-humanization and equality can be achieved from a negative peace, and represents a realistic objective that benefits on both macro and micro levels.

Stability and contact are thus two crucial aspects that can improve ‘thin’ reconciliation theory. If citizens can be engaged with the process through contact and contentedness, a more substantial reconciliation might occur.

Conclusion

This essay argued that despite unrealistic expectations associated with ‘thick’ reconciliation, the practical realities and moral intent offered by ‘thin’ reconciliation thus far make it an ‘appropriate term’ in post-conflict scenarios. It has done this by first analysing reconciliation from a ‘thick’ peace-building perspective—pinpointing assumptions and conceptual themes that are counterproductive for achieving reconciliation. Second, it considered more minimalist approaches that result in functional reconciliation, and functional societies, and how these reduced expectations permit a more process-oriented approach to reconciliation. Third, in recognition that ‘thin’ reconciliation exhibits the most success in establishing non-violence, the essay took this important first step, and modified it to make it more inclusive of victims, perpetrators, and bystanders. Proponents of regenerative reconciliation must lower their conceptual demands, avoiding theoretical frameworks that explicitly target reconciliation itself as the goal of reconciliation. Instead, practitioners should first focus on stabilizing the state, offering victims a newfound sense of security and economic hope—which is what victims typically desire in the first place.[52] As a result, contentedness will improve, easing fears about engaging in a painful process. This essay still advocates a negative-peace approach, but there must be a greater emphasis placed on contact. Although co-existence is important, the process must go on to at least try and achieve something greater. Without micro-level engagement, the minimal levels of trust and justice will stagnate and possibly turn poisonous, resulting in unsustainable peace and, potentially, new violence.

References

African Business (2012) ‘Angola: Rise of a new superpower?’, African Business, June 2012, 48-63 accessed [23/05/2014] available at http://www.minbos.com/assets/documents/mediaresearch/pages48-63-from-ab0612.pdf.

Aliyev H (2011) ‘Aid efficiency in an armed conflict: the role of civil society in the escalation of violence in the North Caucasus’, Institute for International Law of Peace and Armed Conflict (Working Paper Series), 1, 1-80.

Bar-Tal D & Benninck GH (2004) ‘The nature of reconciliation as an outcome and a process’, in Bar-Simon-Tov Y (ed), From Conflict Resolution to Reconciliation. OUP: Oxford, 11-38.

BBC (2006) ‘Timeline: Northern Ireland’s road to peace’, BBC News Website, accessed [18/05/2014] available at http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/northern_ireland/4072261.stm

BBC (2014) ‘David Cameron: ‘All time high for Anglo-Irish relations’, BBC News Website, accessed [18/05/2014] available at http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-northern-ireland-26527087

Bloomfield D, Barnes T & Huyse L (eds.) (2003) Reconciliation After Violent Conflict: A Handbook, IDEA: Stockholm.

Bloomfield D (2006) ‘On good terms: clarifying reconciliation’, Berghof Report (Berghof Research Center for Constructive Conflict Management), 14 (1), 1-42.

CIA World Factbook (2014) ‘The World Factbook (GDP Per Capita country comparison)’, Central Intelligence Agency, accessed [26/05/2014] available at https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-world-factbook/rankorder/2004rank.html.

Clark JN (2012) ‘Reflections on trust and reconciliation’, International Journal of Human Rights, 16 (2), 239-256.

Clark JN (2009) ‘From negative to positive peace: the case of Bosnia and Hercegovina’, Journal of Human Rights, 8 (4), 360-384.

Crocker DA (2000) ‘Retribution and reconciliation’, Institute for Philosophy and Public Policy, 20 (1), 1-6.

De Vos CM (2012) (Review) ‘Foregrounding the ‘Local’: Place-based approaches to transitional justice’, International Journal of Transitional Justice, 6 (1), 374-382.

Drumbl M (2000) ‘Punishment, postgenocide: From guilt to shame to civis in Rwanda’, NYU Law Review, 75 (5) 1221-1326

De Groot OJ (2010) ‘The spillover effects of conflict on economic growth in neighbouring countries in Africa”, Defence and Peace Economics, 21 (2), 149-164.

Galtung J (1969) ‘Violence, peace and peace research’, Journal of Peace Research, 6 (3), 167-191.

Gormally B & McEvoy K (2009) ‘Dealing with the past in Northern Ireland ‘from below’: an evaluation’, The Community Foundation for Northern Ireland, 1, 1-68.

Hinton AL (2010) Transitional Justice: Global Mechanisms and Local Realities after Genocide and Mass Violence, Rutgers University Press: New Brunswick.

Lederach JP (1997) Building Peace, Sustainable Reconciliation in Divided Societies, United States Institute of Peace Press: Washington DC.

LeGloannec AM (1993) ‘France, Germany, and the New Europe’, in Verheyen D & Søe C (eds.), The

Germans and Their Neighbours, Westview Press: Oxford 13-34.

Mallinder L (2009) ‘Amnesties, the TRC and the false promise of prosecutions in South Africa’, Amnesties, Immunities and Prosecutions Conference – Belfast June 2009, (Presentation).

Maoz I (2011) ‘Does contact work in protracted asymmetrical conflict? Appraising 20 years of reconciliation-aimed encounters between Israeli Jews and Palestinians’, Journal of Peace Research, 48 (1), 115-125

Miall H, Ramsbotham O & Woodhouse T (2005) Contemporary Conflict Resolution, Polity Press: Cambridge.

Monteiro C (2004) ‘From military peace to social justice? The Angolan peace process’, Peace and Reconciliation, 1, 66-67 accessed online 22/05/2014, available at http://www.c-r.org/sites/default/files/Accord%2015_15Peace%20and%20reconciliation_2004_ENG.pdf

Pankhurst D (1999) ‘Issues of justice and reconciliation in complex political emergencies: Conceptualising reconciliation, justice and peace’, Third World Quarterly, 20 (1), 239-255.

Rettig M (2008) ‘Gacaca: Truth, Justice and Reconciliation in Post-Conflict Rwanda?’, African Studies Review, 51 (3), 25-50.

Skaar E, Gloppen S & Suhrke A (eds) (2005) Roads to Reconciliation, Lexington Books: Oxford.

Souto VS (2009) ‘Reconciliation and transitional justice: how to deal with the past and build the future’, Thesis presented for The Certificate-of-Training in United Nations Peace Support Operations (November 2009), 1-52.

Staub E, Pearlman LA, Gubin A & Hagengimana A (2005) ‘Healing, reconciliation, forgiving and the prevention of violence after genocide or mass killing: An intervention and its experimental evaluation in Rwanda’, Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 24 (3), 297-334.

Staub E (1989) The Roots of Evil: The Origins of Genocide and Other Group Violence, Cambridge University Press:Cambridge.

Tiemessen AE (2003) ‘After Arusha: Gacaca justice in post-genocide Rwanda’, Thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts at the University of British Colombia (August 2003), 1-112.

Tutu DM (2000) No Future Without Forgiveness, Doubleday (Random House): New York.

US AID (2013) ‘Key considerations when supporting peace’, USAID Technical Brief, March 2013, 1-8.

Yermakov S (2001) ‘The role of conventional armed forces in the system of European security’, Russia’s Institute for Strategic Studies, 1, March 2001, 1-57.

Zorbas E (2009) ‘What does reconciliation mean? Public transcripts and hidden transcripts in post-Genocide Rwanda’, Journal of Genocide Research, 11 (1), 127-147.

————- (2008) ‘Destruction of Zimbabwe’s backbone industry in pursuit of political power: A qualitative report on events in Zimbabwe’s commercial farming sector since the year 2000’, Report prepared by the Justice for Agriculture Trust & the General Agricultural and Plantation Workers of Zimbabwe, 1-77.

————- (1998) ‘The Belfast Agreement’ otherwise known as the Good Friday Agreement, Northern Ireland Office (UK Government) accessed [25/05/2014] available at https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/136652/agreement.pdf.


[1] Pankhurst D (1999) ‘Issues of justice and reconciliation in complex political emergencies: Conceptualising reconciliation, justice and peace’, Third World Quarterly, 20 (1), 240

[2] Clark JN (2012) ‘Reflections on trust and reconciliation’, International Journal of Human Rights, 16 (2)

[3] Bar-Tal D & Benninck GH (2004) ‘The nature of reconciliation as an outcome and a process’, in Bar-Simon-Tov Y (ed), From Conflict Resolution to Reconciliation. OUP: Oxford, 38

[4] Bloomfield D (2006) ‘On good terms: clarifying reconciliation’, Berghof Report (Berghof Research Center for Constructive Conflict Management), 14 (1)

[5] Ibid, 4

[6] Crocker DA (2000) ‘Retribution and reconciliation’, Institute for Philosophy and Public Policy, 20 (1)

[7] ibid 6

[8] Staub E, Pearlman LA, Gubin A & Hagengimana A (2005) ‘Healing, reconciliation, forgiving and the prevention of violence after genocide or mass killing: An intervention and its experimental evaluation in Rwanda’, Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 24 (3), 301

[9] Galtung J (1969) ‘Violence, peace and peace research’, Journal of Peace Research, 6 (3)

[10] Lederach JP (1997) Building Peace, Sustainable Reconciliation in Divided Societies, United States Institute of Peace Press: Washington DC

[11] Souto VS (2009) ‘Reconciliation and transitional justice: how to deal with the past and build the future’, Thesis presented for The Certificate-of-Training in United Nations Peace Support Operations (November 2009), 12

[12] Staub, supra note 8

[13] Tutu DM (2000) No Future Without Forgiveness, Doubleday (Random House): New York.

[14] Bar-Tal & Benninck supra note 3

[15] Ibid 38

[16] Bloomfield supra note 4 7

[17] ibid 7

[18] Bar-tal & Benninck supra note 3 20

[19] US AID (2013) ‘Key considerations when supporting peace’, USAID Technical Brief, March 2013 3

[20] Yermakov S (2001) ‘The role of conventional armed forces in the system of European security’, Russia’s Institute for Strategic Studies, 1, March 2001, 57

[21] Tiemessen AE (2003) ‘After Arusha: Gacaca justice in post-genocide Rwanda’, Thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts at the University of British Colombia (August 2003), 4

[22] Skaar E, Gloppen S & Suhrke A (eds) (2005) Roads to Reconciliation, Lexington Books: Oxford 112-114

[23] Rettig M (2008) ‘Gacaca: Truth, Justice and Reconciliation in Post-Conflict Rwanda?’, African Studies Review, 51 (3), 25-26

[24] De Vos CM (2012) (Review) ‘Foregrounding the ‘Local’: Place-based approaches to transitional justice’, International Journal of Transitional Justice, 6 (1), 382

[25] Ibid 378

[26] Mallinder L (2009) ‘Amnesties, the TRC and the false promise of prosecutions in South Africa’, Amnesties, Immunities and Prosecutions Conference – Belfast June 2009, (Presentation)

[27] Clark (2012) supra note 2 249

[28] Ibid 248

[29] Bloomfield (2006) supra note 4 6

[30] Clark (2012) supra note 2

[31] Rettig (2000) supra note 25 26

[32] Ibid 26

[33] Bloomfield (2006) supra note 4 13-15

[34] Ibid 13

[35] Bar-Tal & Benninck supra note 3 27

[36] BBC (2006) ‘Timeline: Northern Ireland’s road to peace’, BBC News Website, (see references for website)

[37] BBC (2014) ‘David Cameron: ‘All time high for Anglo-Irish relations’, BBC News Website, (see references for website)

[38] Bar-Tal & Benninck supra note 3 27

[39] Maoz I (2011) ‘Does contact work in protracted asymmetrical conflict? Appraising 20 years of reconciliation-aimed encounters between Israeli Jews and Palestinians’, Journal of Peace Research, 48 (1), 118-119

[40] LeGloannec AM (1993) ‘France, Germany, and the New Europe’, in Verheyen D & Søe C (eds.), The Germans and Their Neighbours, Westview Press: Oxford

[41] Staub E (1989) The Roots of Evil: The Origins of Genocide and Other Group Violence, Cambridge University Press:Cambridge 278

[42] ——— (1998) ‘The Belfast Agreement’ otherwise known as the Good Friday Agreement, Northern Ireland Office (UK Government) (see references for website)

[43] Gormally B & McEvoy K (2009) ‘Dealing with the past in Northern Ireland ‘from below’: an evaluation’, The Community Foundation for Northern Ireland, 1 15

[44] Aliyev H (2011) ‘Aid efficiency in an armed conflict: the role of civil society in the escalation of violence in the North Caucasus’, Institute for International Law of Peace and Armed Conflict (Working Paper Series)

[45] Bloomfield D, Barnes T & Huyse L (eds.) (2003) Reconciliation After Violent Conflict: A Handbook, IDEA: Stockholm 34-40 and Monteiro C (2004) ‘From military peace to social justice? The Angolan peace process’, Peace and Reconciliation, 1, 66

[46] Ibid (and page numbers)

[47] African Business (2012) ‘Angola: Rise of a new superpower?’, African Business, June 2012 (see references for website)

[48] ——— (2008) ‘Destruction of Zimbabwe’s backbone industry in pursuit of political power: A qualitative report on events in Zimbabwe’s commercial farming sector since the year 2000’, Report prepared by the Justice for Agriculture Trust & the General Agricultural and Plantation Workers of Zimbabwe

[49] CIA World Factbook (2014) ‘The World Factbook (GDP Per Capita country comparison)’, Central Intelligence Agency, (see references for website)

[50] De Groot OJ (2010) ‘The spillover effects of conflict on economic growth in neighbouring countries in Africa”, Defence and Peace Economics, 21 (21)

[51] Bloomfield (2006) supra note 4 20-28

[52] Zorbas E (2009) ‘What does reconciliation mean? Public transcripts and hidden transcripts in post-Genocide Rwanda’, Journal of Genocide Research, 11 (1), 127-130


Written by: Matthew Richmond
Written at: University of Sheffield
Written for: Janine Clark
Date written: May 2014

Further Reading on E-International Relations

Please Consider Donating

Before you download your free e-book, please consider donating to support open access publishing.

E-IR is an independent non-profit publisher run by an all volunteer team. Your donations allow us to invest in new open access titles and pay our bandwidth bills to ensure we keep our existing titles free to view. Any amount, in any currency, is appreciated. Many thanks!

Donations are voluntary and not required to download the e-book - your link to download is below.

Subscribe

Get our weekly email